Copernicus versus the scientific method

1534-1560

I have to confess that for a long time I didn’t really “get” Copernicus. That is to say, while I knew that Copernicus is right and Ptolemy is wrong, I wasn’t clear on just why Copernicus had a better scientific theory, partly because I didn’t bother understanding Ptolemy. So here’s a brief summary of the two. (Howard Margolis’s book helped me out.) There’s a larger point here: what makes Copernicus’s theory better doesn’t quite fit with a lot of pronouncements about “the Scientific Method.”

First, a diagram that illustrates Ptolemy’s model.

ptolemy

To account for the motion of the planets, Ptolemy needed to assume that the five planets (not counting the sun and moon) have both cycles (the big circles) and epicycles (the little circles). If you’re going to put Earth at the center of the system, then you have to have epicycles to account for the motions of the planets, like the retrograde motions where planets seem to go backwards.

Here’s something to note about this diagram: some of the cycles and epicycles vary independently, while others are exactly tied to the motions of the sun. For Mercury and Venus, the epicycles vary independently, taking different periods of time (88 days, 225 days) to complete a circuit. Their cycles, by contrast, take exactly one Earth year to complete a circuit. Furthermore, the deferent, the point at center of each epicycle, is always exactly in line with the sun. For Mars, Jupiter and Saturn on the other hand, it’s the other way around. The cycles vary independently (1.88, 11.86, and 29.46 years to make a complete circuit). But the epicycles take exactly one Earth year to complete a circuit. Furthermore, in each case the line from deferent to planet is exactly parallel to the line from Earth to Sun. Note that it’s hard to see any reason why the epicycle for Jupiter, say, couldn’t take 3.14 years to complete a circuit. But instead somehow, mysteriously, it’s connected with the sun’s motion around the earth.

A large fraction of diagrams on the web purporting to illustrate Ptolemaic astronomy, including the one below, get this crucial point wrong! They show higgledy-piggledy non-parallel deferent/planet lines, pointing any which way. This makes it impossible to understand why Copernicus had a better theory. So I’m not the only person not to get Ptolemy.

ptolemy wrong

This illustration misrepresents Ptolemy’s model. It correctly shows the deferents for Mercury and Venus along the Earth-to-Sun line, but shows inconsistent and incorrect deferent-to-planet lines for Mars, Jupiter and Saturn.

Copernicus’s model, by contrast, doesn’t just replace five circles (the cycles for Mercury and Venus, and the epicycles for Mars, Jupiter and Saturn) with one (for the Earth going around the Sun). It also automatically explains why the five superfluous cycles show an otherwise unexplained synchronic parallelism.

copernic

People who read Copernicus 1543 book carefully (not many at first) could see he had a real explanation for something that’s just a mysterious coincidence in Ptolemy. But contrary to what you may have heard, and what students get taught, about the Scientific Method, Copernicus did not formulate a hypothesis and then collect data to test his hypothesis, and show that it made the right predictions. Ptolemy and Copernicus make the same predictions about where the planets will appear in the sky. (Both are slightly off because they assume circular rather than elliptical orbits, and add some further kludges to correct for this.) Eventually other scientists would gather data in support of Copernicus. Galileo’s observation of the phases of Venus was the real clincher; you can see that under the Ptolemaic scheme you’ll never see a “full” Venus. But the explanatory economy of Copernicus’ theory was a very strong reason for believing in it even before that.

Fortunately, there is a modern theory of how induction works – Solomonoff induction – that can explain why Copernicanism is a better theory. According Ray Solomonoff, induction has two parts. First there is Bayes’ Rule. Bayes’ Rule is an application of probability theory that tells you how you should revise probability estimates in the face of new evidence. Eliezer Yudkowsky gives one of the best introductions around to a counter-intuitive approach that has become enormously influential in recent years. (It’s fun to read too).

But Bayes’ Rule is only part of the story. The rule assumes that you have already assigned some prior probabilities to events before you look at the evidence. And where do scientists get their prior probabilities? Yudkowsky gives one answer: “There’s a small cluttered antique shop in a back alley of San Francisco’s Chinatown. Don’t ask about the bronze rat.” Solomonoff offers a different answer. He argues that we can use the theory of algorithmic complexity, as developed by Kolmogorov, to assign prior probabilities. Roughly, if your theory were turned into a computer program, how long would the program be? The longer the program, the lower the prior probability, where probabilities fall off exponentially with length of program, and are weighted to sum to one. Suppose I give you a sequence of numbers corresponding to the first 1000 decimal digits of π. A computer program to calculate the first 1000 digits of π is going to be a lot shorter than just a list of the first 1000 digits, so the theory that I generated the list by calculating π is astronomically more likely than the theory that I generated the list at random. This is a formalization of Occam’s Razor, that simple explanations with fewer working parts are better.

So collecting evidence in support of a theory is part of good induction. But proposing more economical theories, accounting for more data with fewer working parts, is another part. Sometimes a new theory is so much better than the alternatives that we can assign it a much higher likelihood even before we collect more evidence. With Copernicus, explaining some striking coincidences which were otherwise unexplained, this was the first act in the modern Scientific Revolution.

This isn’t just a matter of historical interest. Physicists now, as they close in (hopefully) on a final theory of fundamental physics find themselves in a similar situation to Copernicus. Our best looking theory – some version of string theory – provides immense explanatory economy (or so we’re told), but just now is difficult or impossible to test. Here’s an article on the conundrums this poses for philosophy of science and the “scientific method.”

6 thoughts on “Copernicus versus the scientific method

  1. Sid Winter

    Yes. And then there was Thomas Kuhn and his books: The Copernican Revolution, and The Structure of Scientific Revolutions. I don’t see his name; have you advanced the argument beyond what he offered? For me, the stories about prior probabilities sound completely bogus. Where’s the support for THAT theory? Not as a mental exercise, but of predictive value.

    Like

    Reply
    1. logarithmichistory Post author

      I’ve read The Structure of Scientific Revolutions, but not the other. Contra Kuhn, Ptolemy and Copernicus are not incommensurable. Even before Galileo observed the phases of Venus, which really settled the argument (or should have), it was clear to those who understood Copernicus that he had a better explanation than Ptolemy, for the reasons I set out above. Ptolemy and Copernicus are not playing two different games. They are playing the same game, and Copernicus is way ahead.

      Solomonoff induction is a big topic. Here’s an introduction https://www.lesswrong.com/posts/p3b5T8YbijEXDAfmR/intuitive-explanation-of-solomonoff-induction

      Like

      Reply
  2. Marc Robbins

    Calling Copernicus’s theory better than that of Ptolemy is retrofitting our notion of science to an earlier age. People back then weren’t looking for great theories; they were looking for better predictions. The problem for Ptolemy’s model was that it was getting worse and worse for predicting when Easter should occur. Copernicus thought the heliocentric model would fix that. It turns out the simple heliocentric model performed worse than the geocentric, so Copernicus layered on epicycles, equants, etc until it fit the data, though was no better than Ptolemy at prediction.

    The conundrum was finally resolved by Kepler (not really Galileo) who made the breakthrough of positing elliptical orbits. (Which also paved the way for Newton’s gravitational explanation of orbit mechanics.)

    Kuhn lays all this out brilliantly in “The Copernican Revolution.” I highly recommend it to one and all.

    Like

    Reply
    1. logarithmichistory Post author

      Not totally. Both the Ptolemaic and Copernican systems had to add some extra kludges – extra epicycles (sort of epi-epicycles), and an offset that put the center of rotation a little away from the Earth/Sun – to fit the data. Kepler eventually showed that the solution was not circles on top of circles, but a different conic section – an ellipse.

      Like

      Reply
  3. bleikind

    Dear Prof. History,
    The Copernican theory requires the existence of stellar parallax, and this fact was known to astronomers of the time. Ptolemy’s theory, however, does not require this. It seemed implausible to that time’s astronomers that the realm of the fixed stars should be so far away as to render parallax unobserved if Earth orbited the Sun. Thus the Copernican theory had a major prediction that was not observed until the 19th century.
    In addition to the phases or Venus, which contradicted Ptolemy and confirmed Copernicus, Galileo also observed the four large moons of Jupiter, which appeared to orbit the great planet as if it were a small model of the larger Solar System.
    Bernard Leikind

    Like

    Reply

Leave a Reply

Fill in your details below or click an icon to log in:

WordPress.com Logo

You are commenting using your WordPress.com account. Log Out /  Change )

Google photo

You are commenting using your Google account. Log Out /  Change )

Twitter picture

You are commenting using your Twitter account. Log Out /  Change )

Facebook photo

You are commenting using your Facebook account. Log Out /  Change )

Connecting to %s